When arguing points in psychology and psychiatry with folks
from all ends of the academic political spectrum, it’s easy to see how people
become emotionally attached to certain ideas (for whatever internal reasons)
and take the position that, “My mind is made up; don’t confuse with me with
facts."
Two of their tricks in arguing are:
- To use a word that has several different senses or referents, and then subtly shift how they are using the word as the argument progresses without admitting that that is what they are doing.
- Living their lives as if they really don’t believe a word they are saying.
First, what is depression?
In his great new book, A New
Unified Theory of Psychology, my
colleague from the Unified Psychotherapy Project, Gregg Henriques, quotes Ingram and Siegle, “The label depression has
been used to discuss a mood state, a symptom, a syndrome…a mood disorder, or a
disease associated with structural abnormalities.”
Gregg Henriques |
[A syndrome is a group of symptoms and/or behaviors that seem to cluster together in many individuals, creates distress or dysfunction, does not include certain other symptoms or behaviors, and has a definitive epidemiology (the incidence and distribution of a disorder in a population, and the sum of the factors controlling its presence or absence].
These alternate definitions of depression are highly relevant to the question currently being batted around so fervently by all sides, “Do antidepressants work for depression?”
The answer to the question depends on which definition is being used in the debates. Especially online, it’s very difficult to tell. Obviously, if by “depression” we mean a mood state, then of course antidepressants do not always “work.” If you are merely unhappy about living in a bad situation, taking an antidepressant will in most cases be a colossal waste of your time and money.
Well, what if it’s a syndrome? Well, at least according to the DSM, which
many people seem to use when it suits their purpose but disparage when it does not,
there are, at the very minimum, at least four completely different “syndromes”
of depression: Major Depression (with or
without the “melancholic” specifier), dysthymia, adjustment disorder with
depression, and depression caused by a medical condition or an outside
substance like a drug. So in a “debate,”
which one are we talking about here?
In discussions of studies of the effects of antidepressants, this question is often fudged. Rather than using the names for the two different syndromes major depression and dysthymia, debaters tend to use the terms "mild to moderate depression" and "severe depression." The "mild to moderate" depression seen in studies is actually much more likely to be dysthymia, while the severe ones are more likely to be major depression.
In discussions of studies of the effects of antidepressants, this question is often fudged. Rather than using the names for the two different syndromes major depression and dysthymia, debaters tend to use the terms "mild to moderate depression" and "severe depression." The "mild to moderate" depression seen in studies is actually much more likely to be dysthymia, while the severe ones are more likely to be major depression.
Clinically, major depression is more likely to respond to antidepressants,
while dysthymia is less likely to. This is complicated
by the fact that the definitions of the syndromes overlap to some degree, but making a
clinical decision is what medical education is supposed to be about – or at
least theoretically.
The anti-antidepressant crowd
loves to point out that recent "meta-studies" show that in mild to
moderate "depression," antidepressants are often no better than
placebos. They also conveniently love to ignore the fact that in the
exact same meta-studies, the drugs are shown to be highly effective for severe
"depression."
Actually, the use of the word depression is being used here to describe two
very different syndromes, but no one mentions that!
Even the president of the
American Psychiatric Association, John Oldham, was guilty of this confusion of
terms in a recent editorial in Psychiatric
News.
By the way, if you don’t think defining syndromes based on symptomatic and other variables is a valid
way to identify diseases, then ask yourself how people could tell infectious diseases
apart before we knew about the existence of germs.
These debates also revolve around another question - whether the
syndromes that do tend to respond to drugs are loosely defined mental
disorders, or are actually a “disease associated with structural [brain] abnormalities.”
When this question comes up, the people who think that
psychiatric drugs have to either be “all good for all people” or “all bad for
all people” with nothing in between (you “splitters” know who you are), tend to
presume that we have a scientific understanding of the neurochemical microarchitecture
of the brain that we are not even close to actually having. Since that is the relevant science needed to
answer this question, at present we are unable to definitively answer it, so we can only
make judgments based on a variety of indirect evidence.
The scientific task is made particularly complicated by the
existence of neural plasticity and epigenetics.
Neural plasticity means that the structure and function of the brain changes significantly in response to persistent environmental demands. This happens in normals. For example, the part of the brain that controls finger movement is significantly larger in concert violinists than it is in average controls. So does this mean that being a concert violinist is a disease? I don’t think so.
Neural plasticity means that the structure and function of the brain changes significantly in response to persistent environmental demands. This happens in normals. For example, the part of the brain that controls finger movement is significantly larger in concert violinists than it is in average controls. So does this mean that being a concert violinist is a disease? I don’t think so.
Epigenetic influences, loosely translated, means that most
genes in any given cell have a switch that turns them off or on – a switch which is also activated in
response to environmental contingencies. So, if the average brain of someone with a given psychiatric
syndrome seems to be significantly different than the average brain of someone
who does not, does this mean that the syndrome is a normal variant caused by a
conditioned response, or evidence of a diseased brain? With our current knowledge of neurochemical
brain microarchitecture being so minimal, we cannot answer that question for
certain.
If there are a very large number of brain differences that are unique to a disorder, and some of the
differences do not seem to be directly related to the syndrome in question
(such as significant differences in eye movements in schizophrenia), then I
lean heavily towards the “disease” model for that syndrome. If not, then I lean
towards the “normal variant” model. But
I am at least willing to admit that we can’t possibly know for sure given our
current knowledge base. Major Depression
is somewhere near schizophrenia in this regard, whereas dysthymia is not.
The epigenetic issue leads us to my second question: is our
behavior predetermined or do we have free will? Of course, people who take the determinist position do not agree among
themselves as to exactly what factors are making the determination. “Determinism”
when used by an psychoanalyst means determined by prior psychological events;
when used by a radical behaviorist it means determined by prior external events
like rewards and punishments. For family systems folk, it means determined by
collective forces, and for biological psychiatrists, it means determined by
genes.
That so-called doctors and scientists could each completely discount three out of four variables which clearly and undoubtedly
affect human behavior is bizarre in and by itself.
But do any of these determinism types actually live
their lives in a way consistent with their professed belief that when we
think we are freely and willfully making a choice as to how we are going to
behave in a given environment, it is nothing but an illusion? If so, then their belief in this
proposition itself would have been predetermined by one or more of the four
factors, and not by the actual scientific merits of their position! They do not seem to be saying that, do they?
In fact, they live their lives weighing
information and anticipating the future in order to make behavioral choices in
order to meet their goals. When they
stop doing that, then we’ll talk.
Of course, this admittedly still leaves
open the question of the existence of free will. What do I think?
Well, I believe in free will, although
there is no way to actually prove it one way or another. The idea that may answer the question is
actually provided by the radical Skinnerian behaviorists. They start from the proposition that when a
rat is learning to run a maze, if it is rewarded (operantly given positive reinforcement), then the probability that it will behave in the
way that was reinforced increases. (Of
course, if food is used as a reinforcer the rat has to be hungry or else this does not work, but that’s a different issue).
In no case does the provision of positive
reinforcement lead to a 100% chance that the rat will do anything.
In fact, when we look at all four factors
described above, each one increases the odds
that certain behavior will ensue. We
could express this probability mathematically as P = p + e + c + g, where P = the
probability of a certain human behavior taking place at a given point in time, p =
prior psychological experiences, e = external reinforcement by environmental factors, c = collective or social forces impinging on the person, and g = their genome.
I submit that when we add together all four
of these factors, P will still not ever reach 100% - there is no certainty or absolute predictability. If this is true, there would have to be a
fifth factor. Lets call this unknown
factor f.w.
Thanks for another wide-minded blog entry. I believe free-will (as well as self-control and taking responsibility for our own choices) should be promoted and rewarded for the general welfare. I see them as more moral and religious concepts than scientific concepts (in a "Popper" sense), although I am pretty sure that the belief and adhesion to those concepts can be scientifically observed in both behavior and in the brain organization. Anyway, in your opinion, would a deterministic model of human behavior lead to any significant difference in psychology science and practice, compared to one that involves a unknown factor (that we can arbitrarily call free will, god, randomness)?
ReplyDeleteAnyway, I think it is easy to believe that free will is an illusion, as long as it is at the same time believed to be a useful and desirable illusion that needs to be nurtured, cherished and maintained most of the time. Then the inability to suspend disbelief (sorry for the 3 negations) on that particular aspect 99% of the time could become a new mental illness diagnosis.
Hi Stanley,
DeleteHi Mr. Holmes.
Thanks for your comment.
If determinism were true, psychotherapy would be a lot easier than it actually is - and a lot less interesting to do.
Since acting as if an illusion were real involves lying to oneself, I would question how useful it would be in the long run.
Thanks for you answer. You convinced me that accepting some illusions is a dangerous slope. May I try another cognitive structure: what if the absence of free-will is seen as having a predetermined destiny, but absolutely no way of knowing that destiny because of both the quasi-infinite number of variables, and the chaotic aspect of the system (another way to say it: past events were ineluctable, but a lot of hope/uncertainty is allowed for the future). Would you be comfortable simply hoping/believing your personal destiny is to be as rational and as scientific as possible, to know yourself, to be self-aware, to make good choices (any setback is a temporary blip), and that part of the destiny of humanity is to minimize mental illness (and many other valuable things), and that you are most likely a significant agent in realizing that destiny. How do you make a difference between the impossibility of knowing a deterministic future, and a really indeterministic future? Aren't those two formulations scientifically equivalent in every aspect except language formulation (even if they correspond to two different religious views).
ReplyDeleteA great philosophical question: Are we predetermined but unable to predict or not predetermined at all, and would the answer really make any difference?
DeleteUnfortunately, I don't think there is any way we will ever be able to answer that. We can only other speculate about the ultimate nature of consciousness, matter, and energy. (Not that I mind speculating on this subject, mind you).
David,
ReplyDeleteI wish you could get this published on the front page of the Psychiatric Times. I suspect there is little exposure or encouragement of this type of analysis in mainstream psychiatry residency programs these days. Certainly, the equation you have proposed cannot even be formulated without the life narrative, which is sorely lacking in the current EHR era. I will certainly pass it on to my colleagues. You are always worth reading!
Even if there were 4 (or 5, or 9) factors determining any individual's behavior at a certain time, they most likely exist in varying proportions across individuals.
ReplyDeleteThen there is the inherent weakness in P, which requires specifying a date for the phenomenon. P requires being able to specify the emergence of b behavior at d date given the mix of p, e, c, g and various f.w.s (or, as I'd prefer to call them, fwiws).
It's unlikely the factors themselves can ever be anything but estimations. (Gene testing? See http://www.medpagetoday.com/MeetingCoverage/AACRMeeting/31985 )
I don't doubt b is multifactorial; even given hundreds of predictive factors, I don't believe P can ever be anywhere near 100% (probably more like 30%). But aspiring to such can keep researchers occupied for decades.
And of course we are constantly interacting with, being influenced by, and trying to influence many other people, each with their own unique combination of prior influences.
DeleteNot to mention the fact that we are constantly confronted with new situations that we have never even been in before.
This is excellent. Thank you for writing this. You need a wider audience. This type of writing is sorely lacking on the topic of psychiatry.
ReplyDelete